04381nam 22006735 450 991048361520332120200919134235.03-319-22738-610.1007/978-3-319-22738-2(CKB)3710000000494185(EBL)4068124(SSID)ssj0001585431(PQKBManifestationID)16263033(PQKBTitleCode)TC0001585431(PQKBWorkID)14864305(PQKB)11604444(DE-He213)978-3-319-22738-2(MiAaPQ)EBC4068124(PPN)190527595(EXLCZ)99371000000049418520151022d2015 u| 0engur|n|---|||||txtccrA Pluralist Theory of the Mind /by David Ludwig1st ed. 2015.Cham :Springer International Publishing :Imprint: Springer,2015.1 online resource (207 p.)European Studies in Philosophy of Science,2365-4228 ;2Description based upon print version of record.3-319-22737-8 Includes bibliographical references at the end of each chapters.Introduction -- Pluralism and Scientific Practice -- Beyond Placement Problems -- A Historical Diagnosis -- Part I In Defense of Conceptual Relativity -- Conceptual Relativity in Philosophy -- Conceptual Relativity in Science -- The Demarcation Problem of Conceptual Relativity -- Part II From Conceptual Relativity to Vertical Pluralism -- The Argument from Horizontal Pluralism -- The Argument from Ontological Non-Fundamentalism -- Part III Beyond the Mind-Body Problem -- Consciousness -- Beyond Dualism and Physicalism -- Mental Causation -- Epilogue: Metaphysics in a Complex World.This book challenges common debates in philosophy of mind by questioning the framework of placement problems in contemporary metaphysics. The author argues that placement problems arise when exactly one fundamental ontology serves as the base for all entities, and will propose a pluralist alternative that takes the diversity of our conceptual resources and ontologies seriously.  This general pluralist account is applied to issues in philosophy of mind to argue that contemporary debates about the mind-body problem are built on this problematic framework of placement problems. The starting point is the plurality of ontologies in scientific practice. Not only can we describe the world in terms of physical, biological, or psychological ontologies, but any serious engagement with scientific ontologies will identify more specific ontologies in each domain. For example, there is not one unified ontology for biology, but rather a diversity of scientific specializations with different ontological needs. Based on this account of scientific practice the author argues that there is no reason to assume that  ontological unification must be possible everywhere. Without this ideal, the scope of ontological unification turns out to be an open empirical question and there is no need to present unification failures as philosophically puzzling “placement problems”.European Studies in Philosophy of Science,2365-4228 ;2Philosophy and sciencePhilosophy of mindMetaphysicsBiology—PhilosophyPhilosophy of Sciencehttps://scigraph.springernature.com/ontologies/product-market-codes/E34000Philosophy of Mindhttps://scigraph.springernature.com/ontologies/product-market-codes/E31000Metaphysicshttps://scigraph.springernature.com/ontologies/product-market-codes/E18000Philosophy of Biologyhttps://scigraph.springernature.com/ontologies/product-market-codes/E34010Philosophy and science.Philosophy of mind.Metaphysics.Biology—Philosophy.Philosophy of Science.Philosophy of Mind.Metaphysics.Philosophy of Biology.100Ludwig Davidauthttp://id.loc.gov/vocabulary/relators/aut1225665BOOK9910483615203321A Pluralist Theory of the Mind2845708UNINA